Wikipedia:Reference desk/Archives/Mathematics/2010 January 22
Mathematics desk | ||
---|---|---|
< January 21 | << Dec | January | Feb >> | January 23 > |
Welcome to the Wikipedia Mathematics Reference Desk Archives |
---|
The page you are currently viewing is an archive page. While you can leave answers for any questions shown below, please ask new questions on one of the current reference desk pages. |
January 22
[edit]Weaker versions of Fermat's Last Theorem
[edit]Andrew Wiles proved that Fermat's Last Theorem is true, i.e. that for the equation , there are no solutions where a, b, c and n are all natural numbers and n is greater than 2. What if we weaken the preconditions? If we allow at least one of a, b, and c to be any positive real, then it is trivially true that has solutions, because it reduces to checking whether is a positive real, and such a positive real always exists. But what if we say that a, b, and c have to be natural numbers, but n can be any positive real? What can we say about what solutions exist for what values of n? JIP | Talk 07:04, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- For all natural numbers (a, b, c) such that c > a and c > b and c < a + b there exists a real number n such that . I've discovered a lovely little proof of this, but this edit window is too small to contain it. Dragons flight (talk) 08:04, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- Let me try: ⊿. --Stephan Schulz (talk) 08:25, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- :-) Nice actually you don't need c<a+b (for real numbers 0<a≤b<c or 0<c<a≤b there exists a unique real n; if 0<a≤c≤b no such real n exists). --pma 09:49, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- 63+73>83 but 64+74<84, so there is a solution with a=6, b=7, c=8, and n somewhere between 3 and 4.--RDBury (talk) 13:35, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- I don't have a proof but just thinking it through I'm sure there's an infinity of a solution for n: take e.g. the above and double all the numbers. The solution will be the same but you can also modify a, b and c to get a slightly different equation with a different solution. Rinse and repeat with ever bigger numbers. There should be equations with solutions and so values for n. But there are real numbers in any interval, so an n picked at random will not be a solution. I don't know if you can say anything about the values for n other than this. --JohnBlackburnewordsdeeds 13:49, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- Strictly speaking there are at least real numbers in any interval. AndrewWTaylor (talk) 14:15, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- I don't have a proof but just thinking it through I'm sure there's an infinity of a solution for n: take e.g. the above and double all the numbers. The solution will be the same but you can also modify a, b and c to get a slightly different equation with a different solution. Rinse and repeat with ever bigger numbers. There should be equations with solutions and so values for n. But there are real numbers in any interval, so an n picked at random will not be a solution. I don't know if you can say anything about the values for n other than this. --JohnBlackburnewordsdeeds 13:49, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- The homogeneity of the equation suggests an alternative proof to the one which (I assume) Dragons flight had in mind. Show that for any real u, v such that 0 < u < 1 and 0 < v < 1 there is a real w > 0 such that . Then take u = a/c and v = b/c. Gandalf61 (talk) 14:31, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- If w = 0 then . The limit as w→+∞ is 0. So by continuity there is a value of w between 0 and +∞ where the expression =1. There are only countably many choices for u and v so the number of possible values for w is countable. In particular Fermat's last theorem says w can't be an integer greater than 3. It probably wouldn't be hard to show the possible ws are dense in some interval though. So even though you can't have w=3 you could get w arbitrarily close to 3.--RDBury (talk) 18:04, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- The homogeneity of the equation suggests an alternative proof to the one which (I assume) Dragons flight had in mind. Show that for any real u, v such that 0 < u < 1 and 0 < v < 1 there is a real w > 0 such that . Then take u = a/c and v = b/c. Gandalf61 (talk) 14:31, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- A variation on these lines: for a given positive integer n it's not hard to find countably many solutions in positive integers x,y,z of the Diophantine equation x1/n+y1/n=z1/n. But can we characterize all solutions? In particular, is it necessary that x,y,z are perfect n-th powers? --84.220.119.131 (talk) 22:58, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
Bounds
[edit]Let us assume that a(t) and b(t) are, over ]0,∞[, both real valued and infinitely differentiable functions of the variable t. Furthermore, let us assume that the function c(t) is defined by c(t) = a(t) / b(t). Now, let us assume that the limit of c(t) as t tends towards positive infinity is k, where k is a positive real number. What can we say about a(t) and b(t)? What can we say about anything? Fly by Night (talk) 18:42, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- What sort of things do you want to say? We can say, for example, that b is eventually nonzero (that's the only constraint on b alone, though) and that a and b are eventually of the same sign. Algebraist 18:48, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- I wanted something more substantial than that. If we have two non-zero integers, say a and b, then we can form the number a/b. The integers cross the integers form a quotient space, namely the rational numbers: we say that (a,b) is in the same class as (c,d) if and only if ad = bc. Is their some kind of classification of pair of functions given a limit of their quotient? Fly by Night (talk) 19:05, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
- There might be two equivalence relations. Define A(b, k) the set of functions which have limit k when divided by b, define B(a, k) the set of functions which have limit k when multiplied by a. My guess is that for every k, for every triplett of functions b, x, y it is true that: x in A(b, k) and y in A(b, k) => B(x, k) = B(y, k). Then B(A(b, k), k) could be an equivalence class for b. Maybe k is also irrelevant, so we get the class "all functions with similar limit behaviour as b". I don't know if that is actually true, but it sounds interesting and superficially plausible. —Preceding unsigned comment added by 80.226.1.7 (talk) 15:45, 23 January 2010 (UTC)
- I wanted something more substantial than that. If we have two non-zero integers, say a and b, then we can form the number a/b. The integers cross the integers form a quotient space, namely the rational numbers: we say that (a,b) is in the same class as (c,d) if and only if ad = bc. Is their some kind of classification of pair of functions given a limit of their quotient? Fly by Night (talk) 19:05, 22 January 2010 (UTC)
Simplify by substituting t=1/x because an infinite t is more confusing than a zero x. Pick an arbitrary positive continuous function C(x) with C(0)=k. Pick an arbitrary positive continuous function B(x). Define A(x)=B(x)C(x). All you can say is that limx→0A(x)/B(x)=k. Bo Jacoby (talk) 22:25, 22 January 2010 (UTC).